The Action and Power of the Universe

Any critical thoughts (constructive or otherwise) would be appreciated on the following short draft. It is an outline of thoughts to be developed in greater depth for an upcoming paper. The thought-outline itself will be presented as such a schema (a “comunicación”) in Spanish translation at the upcoming IV Congreso Internacional de Filosofía Tomista in Santiago, Chile.

MilkyWayPanorama
From horizon to horizon, via the Milky Way. [P. HORÁLEK / ESO; website]

 

The Action and Power of the Universe:
Operari Sequitur Esse and the Principle of Least Action

1. Introduction

This presentation outlines a small part of my exploration of the nature of Aristotelian form and its relationships to modern scientific cosmology. In this presentation, we discuss the principle of least action (PLA) and its connection to the axiom that the action of a thing follows upon its being (operari sequitur esse). We will first look at some examples of the PLA and then go through a three-stage process of trying to understand it more metaphysically. We will not attend too much to the mathematical formalism that is essential to expressing the principle.⁠1 Hopefully, despite prescinding from the mathematics, we will attend to the prior conditions of being that give physical things characteristics such as the PLA, determining them in themselves and in relationship to each other.

2. The deepest principle of nature?

The PLA is called one of the deepest principles of nature. What exactly is it? Consider an analogy given by the physicist Richard Feynman.⁠2 A lifeguard sees a swimmer struggling out in the waves some distance along the beach from where he is. What is the most efficient path from the lifeguard station to the struggling swimmer? Would it be fastest to run along the beach first and then swim out to sea on a path perpendicular to the beach? Or is the direct path the fastest, a straight line between the lifeguard’s initial position and the endangered swimmer? The answer is neither—the fastest path is somewhere in between. This governing principle between the beginning and endpoint of a system of motion, for a given least or minimum amount of time and energy invested, is the PLA.

The PLA as a condition of physical systems is ubiquitous—this is an empirical discovery of modern physics. The behavior of light, solids, liquids, and gases obeys this principle. The PLA applies to the behavior of quantum phenomena at the smallest scales as well as the behavior of systems of galaxies and of the universe at the largest scales. Thus, by induction, the PLA seems to qualify as a universal principle—it holds over all scales and all states of matter (that is, mass and energy).

More formally, the “action” that is made “least” by this principle is a quantity that one obtains by the definite integral of the difference between the kinetic and potential energy of a physical system (taken between a starting time and an ending time). For all the conceptually possible paths of motion for a given system, nature uses the path where this integral sum is zero—the action is minimized.⁠3 Nature decides to economize and save both time and energy.⁠4 Let us turn to investigate this in three aporetic stages.

3. Is the PLA a cause or an effect?

The first stage is to set up a question of priority: Is the PLA a cause or an effect? This can be framed in terms of the axiom operari sequitur esse: a thing’s operation follows upon the mode of its being. There is a proportion between a substance and its action or passion in the world; again, there is a proportion between the nature of a physical thing (the cause) and what it does by nature (the effect). We can ask this question of causal priority with regard to the PLA: “Does the [PLA] guide physical systems such that action is [minimized], or do the fundamental dispositions of objects have a modal character that determines the [minimized] quantities of action inherent to all physical systems?”⁠5 Is the PLA a cause or an effect? 

Now, a neo-Platonistic view of universals would make the PLA a cause, the governing condition of physical interaction.⁠6 What about views that make the PLA an effect? A first possible answer is a Humean one. The authors Smart and Thébault write: “According to Humean Supervenience, the PLA is a contingent truth that supervenes on the [spatio-temporal] mosaic of property and relation instantiations. For the Humean, the PLA is a law in virtue of the path the physical system follows being that which extremises action.”⁠7 In this case, the PLA is a consequence of the contingent interactions of the “mosaic” of natural phenomena, the matters-of-fact.

If we are not inclined to swallow all the consequences of Humeanism, another answer to our question of priority is a more Aristotelian one. Perhaps the PLA is a global effect of the dispositions of individual objects. Consider the dispositionalism of Brian Ellis in this regard.⁠8 Ellis defends a threefold hierarchy: “[A] hierarchy of natural kinds of objects or substances, one of natural kinds of events or processes, and one of properties or relationships.”⁠9 The PLA fits into the “summit” of the first hierarchy: “At the summit of each hierarchy, I postulate that there is a global natural kind that includes every kind of thing in the corresponding category. The global natural kind in the category of substances is that of the physical system.”⁠10 If this is the case, then the PLA would “be of the essence of the global kind in the category of objects or substances. If this is so, then, of course, every continuing object must be Lagrangian.”⁠11 So, if the PLA is this sort of dispositional effect, it is a strange one, for it constitutes part of the essence of the world, so it is also a type of formal cause.

4. The PLA: one or many?

Discarding the Humean story for the sake of time, let’s stick with the idea that the PLA is some sort of effect that perhaps somehow emerges as a globally essential feature. Yet is the PLA a true feature because of what is true about the natures or dispositions of substances? This second stage looks at the connection between a global behavior and individuals at a local scale.

First, exalt global behavior to an extreme.⁠12 One could claim that “something is a substance if and only if it evolves by the fundamental laws”⁠13 present in the universe. The PLA is such a law. However, if the universe is “the one and only thing that evolves by the fundamental laws,”⁠14 then it would seem to follow that “the cosmos is the one and only substance.”⁠15 We must find unity of being where there is unity of activity—operari sequitur esse. Now, this argument for monism falters, among other reasons, because its second premise assumes more knowledge of the universe as a whole than we currently posses. If we have other reasons against monism—and there are more than one—we need to find a less extreme way to understand the PLA as an effect.

Perhaps this more reserved treatment severs global behaviors from real, local dispositions.⁠16 Anjan Chakravarrty proposes, “Why not think of the relevant dispositions regarding conservation as properties of the system itself, as opposed to properties of the things constituting or inhabiting it?”⁠17 In this sense, a principle such as the PLA would be a property belonging to the world as a system that we can investigate empirically, for “investigation of this sort confirms that this is part of the nature of these systems; they are disposed to behave that way.”⁠18 On this view, the property of “Lagrangianism” is not part of the essence of the global kind “the world” itself but its property, yet not a property of the “the world” because the world is composed (somehow) of the combined dispositions of various individual objects in it.

5. How is the PLA a feature of a world of substances?

Some might find this dispositionalist answer outlined by Chakravarrty unappealing. Might not such global behavior flow from the natures of things both without being eliminatively reduced to those dispositions and without being an adventitious yet empirically true feature of nature at a global scale? Now, implicit in the axiom that the mode of operation follows upon the mode of being is that there could be modes of operations (plural) and thus an array of operations that follow from the being of a substance in a certain order. This order is partially captured in the order among the Thomistic categories of being. Recall the categories of ubi, or “where,” along with action, passion, and orientation (or arrangement, situs). Motion is intricately connected with these four categories, for the quantitative concomitants of motion are expressed in these categories and provide the substructure for the qualitatively teleological character of natural motions.

Consider the 17th-century thought experiment of John Poinsot.⁠19 How exactly is “where” part of the being of a placed thing: is it intrinsic or extrinsic? He asks: “If you were to stipulate that the whole frame of the universe be removed just as before the first creation of things, and a stone were created and set in motion, what would it acquire, if it did not acquire something wholly intrinsic?”⁠20 To be somewhere is to be contained by a place. In a vacuum or void, there is apparently no containing body, but distance still exists. A hot stone could not heat, for there would be no circumscriptive body or medium to be acted upon. John’s solution is as follows: “But if local motion were to exist in a vacuum, it would be imperfect and would acquire ‘a where’ qualifiedly and not simply speaking, but rather a mode of distance or nearness, which is a condition of [having] ‘a where’.”⁠21 Note: a body in a vacuum would acquire a certain condition for a real where or location. This condition is having distance or nearness, presumably to points that are only mentally and not really demarcated in this hypothetical void-cosmos, like a modern coordinate system.⁠22 Today, the conditions of being in a physical “where” are action and reaction relationships between mass and gravitational fields; this is a modern instance of the situatedness of bodies leading to a combination dispositionally, contingently, and yet also extrinsically resulting in behavior conforming to conservation principles and the PLA.⁠23 The ancients and medievals had ”natural place” to express this characteristic of system-level emergent effects in the universe; we have Lagrangians and the PLA. Analogously to the ancients, can we say that the extrinsic features flow from the intrinsic dispositions of things, but not reductively so?

Yes, since the formal constitution of individuals and their dispositions is double-sided. This twin aspect—both intrinsic and extrinsic determination—is a characteristic of formal causality, as St. Thomas writes: “Any creature whatsoever subsists in its own being and has a form through which it is determined as to its species and has an order to something else.”⁠24 Consequently, the key idea is that the forms of physical objects are not merely intrinsic determinations but also extrinsically ground various relations: operari sequitur esse. The forms of individuals are—via these essential, extrinsic, determinable relations—formal parts of a cosmic whole. This comports with the Thomistic idea that the form of the universe—the natural kind of the world—is its very unity of order.⁠25

In review: The natures of things (including their dispositions for physical interactions) require an ordered relationship of individuals to each other. This ordered relationship of individuals to each other, by the axiom operari sequitur esse, requires an ordered relationship through an environment of possible action/passion interactions. This physical environment is encoded by the PLA. The natures of individual objects therefore interact in a way that the PLA encodes—the PLA is an essential accident of a system of natural objects (perhaps it is a mélange of the ancient categories of where, action, passion, and arrangement). However, this PLA-conforming effect is for the sake of the form of the universe, a unity of order (a harmony). This suggests that the PLA is in another respect a cause, a teleological condition for achieving an ordered cosmos. In this way, global behaviors such as the PLA flow from substances with natures that are coordinated within a whole of a certain scale, namely, the universe.


1 My claim will be that, regardless of the mathematics used to express the principle, its interpretation must eventually resolve to non-mathematical claims that are independent of the formalism. So, we will attempt to make sense of the PLA in such a way that any additional mathematical detail or clarity would (at the most) be supportive of the position argued for here or it would (at the least) not conflict with it.

2 I borrow this analogy from Feynman. See Feynman, Richard P. QED: The Strange Theory of Light and Matter. Princeton Science Library (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2014) 51–52. Smart, Benjamin T. H., and Karim P. Y. Thébault. “On the Metaphysics of Least Action,” (Preprint, March 25, 2013) also have a helpful analogy of a “lazy plumber” attempting to lay pipe between a well and his house that involves the least “effort” in pumping energy for a given time. Suppose we have a farmer who wants to connect an outside well to his house by a pipe so he has water for everyday use. The terrain around his house is also somewhat hilly, and he can only lay the pipe overground, not underground. He will also have to pump the water by hand for a certain amount of time every day. So, he wants to lay the pipe so that he needs to exert the least amount of effort in a given time every day when he pumps water. In order to conserve effort, it is not the case that the path the pipe must take is the direct path overground. It will depend upon the terrain between the well and his house. In this example, given the constraints of the terrain and the time available to pump water between the two endpoints (the house and well) the “least amount of effort” corresponds to what we will call the “action”.

3 It is important that these alternative paths are “conceptually” possible; they are “alternatives” in a restricted sense.

4 See Jerome Fee, “Maupertuis, and the Principle of Least Action,” The Scientific Monthly 52, no. 6 (1941): 498: “Whatever else action may be, it is a partnership of time and energy in which neither can be emphasized a shade more than the other.”

5 Benjamin T. H. Smart and Karim P. Y. Thébault, “Dispositions and the Principle of Least Action Revisited,” Analysis 75, no. 3 (2015): 392.

6 One could conceive of the laws of nature as higher-order universals that constitute the necessary relationships between lower-order universals instantiated in the world (à la David Armstrong). Thus, laws of nature such as the PLA, Maxwell’s equations, or gravitational attraction would all be such higher-order universals. A consequence of this view is that the higher-order or more universal law (in this case, the PLA) would be more of a law and more of a cause. Perhaps it is the only law (to avoid overdetermination). If we accept arguments against Platonism (such as variations of the “Third Man”), or maintain that some sort of dispositionalism must be involved, we will be disinclined to accept this explanation of the PLA as a cause.

7 Smart and Thébault, “On the Metaphysics of Least Action,” 16.

8 See Brian Ellis, “Katzav on the Limitations of Dispositionalism,” Analysis 65, no. 1 (January 2005): 90–92, which is in response to Joel Katzav, “Dispositions and the Principle of Least Action.” Analysis 64, no. 3 (July 2004): 206–14. Katzav responds in the same issue: “Ellis on the Limitations of Dispositionalism.” Analysis 65, no. 1 (January 2005): 92–94. The debate is revisited by Benjamin T. H. Smart and Karim P. Y. Thébault in their “Dispositions and the Principle of Least Action Revisited,” Analysis 75, no. 3 (July 2015): 386–95.

9 Ellis, “Katzav on the Limitations of Dispositionalism,” 90–91.

10 Ibid., 91.

11 Ibid., 91–92.

12 This is similar to the monistic argument from nomic regularity proposed by Jonathan Schaffer, “The Action of the Whole,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87, no. 1 (June 1, 2013): 67–87.

13 Ibid., 67.

14 Ibid.

15 Ibid.

16 See Anjan Chakravartty, “Physics, Metaphysics, Dispositions, and Symmetries – à La French,” (forthcoming). His view develops the idea of the world as a member of a natural kind proposed by John Bigelow, Brian Ellis, and Caroline Lierse, “The World as One of a Kind: Natural Necessity and Laws of Nature,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43, no. 3 (1992): 371–88.

17 Chakravartty, “Physics, Metaphysics, Dispositions, and Symmetries.”

18 Ibid.

19 CP:Logica, II, q. 19, a. 33 (p. 548–59 Vives ed.; c. 632 Reiser ed.).

20 Ibid.

21 Ibid.

22 One might recall, in this regard, abstract problems involving the conservation of energy in modern physics such as the gravitational oscillator problem. This thought experiment involves a body falling down a tunnel through the center of the earth, emerging on the other side, and falling back through again, oscillating (in this idealization) ad infinitum.

23 [CITATION TO BE ADDED]

24 St. Thomas, ST, Ia, q. 45, a. 7, c. “Quaelibet enim creatura subsistit in suo esse, et habet formam per quam determinatur ad speciem, et habet ordinem ad aliquid aliud.” (Leon.4.476)

25 [CITATION TO BE ADDED]

Advertisements

One thought on “The Action and Power of the Universe

"Sed contra" or "Distinguo" or "Amplius" below ...

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

w

Connecting to %s